Thursday, March 3, 2022

Cities, Networks, and Globalization I

Chapter 2: Cities, Networks, and Globalization

The material to follow in this chapter fulfills key tasks of the larger project presented by this document.  First, it defines the city as a spatial form.  Second, it defines globalization in relation to the definition of the city.  Finally, it relates the city and globalization to class, preparatory to a consideration of class structural heterogeneity in chapter 3. 

In order to achieve the first of these tasks, I will address the basic problem of space in reference to the Althusserian overdeterminist ontology asserted in chapter 1.  The intention of this explanation is not to rewrite overdeterminist ontology in reference to space but to develop separate imageries of space on both the holistic, closed, determinate field of the structured totality of material processes and the partial, open, and contingent field of theory.  The imagery advanced in regard to the ontological field of theory will be that of the network, constituted as a piece-wise, partial assemblage of space.  It will be the purpose of the first section of this chapter to outline this dual ontological imagery of space and, especially, to define how networks will be understood in this project, comparing and contrasting this definition of networks to that of Actor Network Theory (ANT).  Proceeding beyond the basic effort to define the network, the second section will define the city as a spatial form constituted by networks and the third section will argue that globalization, as a constellation of processes defining distinct networks across space, is articulated through the space of cities. 

The remaining sections of this chapter will seek to elaborate further the distinctiveness of the city, as the urban spatial form, relative to non-urban forms.  The point, in this respect, is that the city is unique as a space for articulation of networked linkages between processes with globally extensive effects.  Moving beyond this particular uniqueness, however, the interrelations of processes in the city, within its hinterlands, and across globally extensive networks produce a particular developmental dynamic that I intend to label incubation.  In development and utilization of this concept, I mean to argue that the profusion of effects from processes internal and external to the city generate a dynamic of continuous economic redevelopment, in the sense described by Jacobs (1970: 125-129) in her conception of a supply-export reciprocating system and the creation of “new work” by cities more generally.  Asserting incubation in relation to the networked-defined spatial form of cities as the basis for development of new production processes in cities, the next two sections will articulate the consequences of incubation to class processes.  The intention, in this regard, will be to argue, on the one hand, that class processes articulate networks over diverse geographic ranges and, on the other hand, that the existence of geographically localized class processes in a given city incubates ranges of other production processes, extending class networks to other nodes internal to the city.  This consideration of the effects of incubation on class processes will constitute the starting point for elaboration of the principal hypothesis of this project that cities incubate heterogeneous class structures, in chapter 3. 

Concluding this brief introduction, the material contained in this chapter attempts to move from a high level of theoretic abstraction, from the field of structured totality, to successively higher levels of theoretically reconstructed concreteness evident in a definition of the city, as an assemblage of networked processes, including class processes.  I make no apologies for the level of abstraction advanced at the outset.  Rather, such a process follows, in part, Marx’s “method,” advanced in the introduction to A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy (1993: 100-108).  That is to say, the methodology followed in this chapter, first, asserts the irreducible complexity of material existence, patterned theoretically by the concept of structured totality, with its own irreducibly complex spatio-temporality (universal space-time).  Beyond this irreducibility of structured totality, I seek to define a basic theoretic concept in the disconnected process with a disconnected spatio-temporality.  Finally, the approach reconstructs the connectedness of processes and the implications of connectedness in space-time (networked space-time).  In my view, the absence of such a theoretic process, linking Althusserian ontological concepts to spatio-temporality, would compromise the ability of this project to conceptualize either the network or the city by depriving these concepts of a solid connection to the Marxist/Althusserian ontology appropriated by this project as its basic theoretic framework.  For this reason, I regard the material contained here as constituting a critical stage in the larger conception of this project. 

Theorizing Space: Sites, Networks, and Nodes


The primary objectives of this section are to integrate space, or, more properly, spatio-temporality, into an overdeterminist Marxist/Althusserian ontology, and, with regard to the field of theory, to develop a conception of networks emanating from overdeterminist ontology.  In securing these objectives, I will, first, describe space-time on the field of structured totality, approaching spatio-temporality in reference to the concept of the site.  I will, then, describe spatio-temporality on the field of theory by pursuing the theoretic dislocation of the site from its context in structured totality.  The intention of this dislocation is to achieve the transformation of the site into a node, constituting the basic unit of a network.  The closing arguments of this section will advance a comparison of this approach to that of Actor Network Theory in order to more thoroughly illuminate the specific theoretic content of my approach to the network in relation to this more developed body of theory. 

Spatio-Temporality of Structured Totality: Sites

As outlined in chapter 1, structured totality constitutes the fundamental ontological concept in Althusserian ontology, describing the collection of all material processes, connected across multiple, hierarchical structures in which every process exists as a loci for determination by every other process, both internally and externally in relation to a given process. 

To proceed further in describing this overdetermination of processes, at each locus processual determinations from past and contemporaneous effects combine to produce a specific, determinate transformation of material existence.  I mean to construe the concept of “effect” utilized, in this regard, in the broadest possible terms, to include the particular transformations of material objects and those of contexts in which individual agents act or other processes otherwise occur.  Thus, the manifestations of use values emerging from a particular production processes in which raw materials, equipment, and labor power have been combined to produce something new may be construed as effects of the production process.  Additionally, emissions of chemical substances, incidental to the same production process, may also be viewed as effects of the production process, which, in turn, shape particular ecological processes through their transmission.  Lastly, the production process may impact myriad other political, economic, cultural, ecological, physical, chemical, biological, etc. processes in particular ways by means of other unspecified effects on the contexts in which these processes occur.  

Every combination of effects is specific, because each combines a unique set of determinations from different, unique sets of overdeterminants.  Some of these overdeterminants may arise from the explosive diffusion of effects of processes in the immediate past.  Others may arise from the accumulated effects of processes in a more distant past over an extended length of time.  Still others may be the effects of a process in the very distant past whose positive effects on the process awaited the appropriate combination of other, more recent effects to achieve the conjunctural realization of some particular outcome. 

These reflections begin to establish an understanding of the temporal dimension of processes in an overdetermined totality.  Time, in these terms, is relational.  As suggested briefly in chapter 1, my use of this terminology follows, in some degree, its use by theorists like Harvey, Massey, Amin, and other who identify the dimensionality of processes and/or things within material existence as a relationship to other such processes and/or things.  Harvey’s specification of the relational concept in regard to spatiality provides the clearest example of what I have in mind here.  Harvey characterizes relational space as a Leibnizian concept defining the dimensionality “contained in objects in the sense that an object can be said to exist only insofar as it contains and represents within itself relationships to other objects” (Harvey, 1973: 13).  More succinctly:

(T)he relational view of space holds there is no such thing as space or time outside of the processes that define them…Processes do not occur in space but define their own spatial frame.  The concept of space is embedded in or internal to process (Harvey, 2006B: 123).

 

The same sort of understanding of the relational concept can be applied with respect to the temporal dimension of processes within overdeterminist ontology.  Time exists as a set of relationships connecting a process to its internal and external overdeterminants, expressing a difference between processes occurring simultaneously and others occurring at successively farther distances into the past.  In this manner, time can only be gauged as a temporal distance between the manifestation of a process and some other process whose effects have overdetermined the first process.  The temporality of a process expresses its simultaneity or non-simultaneity with other processes that effect it as an outcome of overdetermination.  Thus, time is a dimension specific to each process, expressing the trajectory of a process in relation to all other processes.[1] 

Spatiality constitutes the second set of dimensions unique to each process.  Defined again in relational terms at least partly consistent with those of Harvey, spatiality describes the collocated or non-collocated existence of a process with its internal and external overdeterminants, in the limit, in simultaneity.  By extension of this relational logic, the notion of spatial dispersion or distance between processes can be defined in reference to the relative proximity of multiple processes, through which a process may be relatively closer to certain overdeterminants at a temporal instance than it is to others. 

By this understanding, temporal/historical ranges and spatial/geographic scales both exist as relational articulations, internalized to individual processes at specific loci.  Some overdeterminants of a process are collocated with and simultaneous to the process, while others are non-collocated (either internally contained or external, overlapping or entirely distinct and separated) but simultaneous to the process, still others are non-simultaneous but collocated, and still others are neither coextensive nor simultaneous.  The possibilities advanced here map the objective geography and history of a process in relation to its overdeterminants, objective in the sense that they conceptually situate the position of a particular process, at a point/moment in its trajectory, relative to every other process in structured totality.  The notion of such an objective geographic and historical position describes the concept of a site.[2] 

Sites have a geometry and a temporal instance/moment, encompassing all that is internal or organic to the process, including processes constituting the relative boundedness of the site itself.  For example, the class process of surplus labor production has a site, defined by the productive consumption of labor power, the spatial dimensions containing this transformation and the temporal moment in which the transformation occurs or does not occur.  This site is consistent with the notion of the “industrial site,” containing the simultaneous and collocated processes of surplus production and appropriation, as described by Ruccio et al (1991).  The site has boundaries, however tangible or intangible, that delimit the spatial dimensions of the process relative to what is external to it at each temporal instance/moment.  Internal to those boundaries, the class process of production contains certain overdeterminate processes, involving biological, physical, and chemical transformations (e.g. composites of chemically transformative processes changing raw materials into new use values) and mental, emotional, political, cultural, and economic processes whose outcomes effect the productive consumption of labor power. 

The site of the surplus production process contains the sites of many of its overdeterminants, but containment of these sites may be transitory.  Other processes may invade or escape the site of production at different moments, and the effects of these processes on the production process may change in relation to their containment or externalization.  For example, the sites of particular non-class social processes, involving workers engaged in a surplus production process and overdetermining the process, may be contained by the space of the production process at certain times and spill over or transport themselves to other sites at other times, with changes in location having effects on the production process.           

Extending this understanding of the site to encompass the aggregate, the spatio-temporality of structured totality, as the assemblage of all mutually constituted/mutually constitutive material processes, constitutes a seamless, universal, objective space-time, as the assemblage of all processual sites.  Such a universal space-time is decentered and devoid of any temporal baseline, because it constitutes an irreducibly complex aggregation of processes, each with its own relational centeredness (as individual loci), temporal baseline, and trajectory, defined by its relationship to all other processes.  In this sense, universal space-time can only be mapped in reference to individual processual sites – the spatio-temporality of structured totality, per se, cannot be mapped. 

More practically, this project asserts that the irreducible complexity implied by overdetermination precludes any objective mapping on the ontological field of structured totality.  To conceptualize such a mapping of individual processes would amount to the tracing of connections, in the transmission of effects, between processual sites across both infinitely expansive spatial and temporal dimensions.  Again, by asserting the unapproachable conditions for objective spatio-temporality, this project seeks to reinforce the performative character of geographic and historical theorization and analysis.  Mappings of space-time relationships between processes can only be partial in their articulation, and the purpose for engaging in such theorizations and analyses can only be to shape the way the reality of space-time is understood and, hence, lived.  Performative mappings do not belong to the objective and unapproachable background of totality but to the field of theory. 

Spatio-Temporality of Theory: Networks and Nodes

Abstracting from the irreducible complexity of structured totality and, thus, from the universal space-time it constitutes, the Marxian method implies that a theoretic ontology must isolate a simplified processual unit – a single locus for overdetermination stripped of its connections to processual overdeterminants – and reconstruct its constitutive linkages to other processes.[3]  In regard to space-time, the site, as a universally connected position of a given process in mutually constitutive relation to its overdeterminants, must be emptied of its spatio-temporality in order to reconstruct, in a piece-wise manner, the spatio-temporality of its connections to other processual sites. 

            In a spaceless-timeless ontology, the theoretic reconstruction of processual connections constitutes the articulation of structures, as series of processes defined by a particular, theoretically identified relationship between processes (e.g. the class structure).  In reference to space-time, reconstruction of the spatio-temporality of structures defines a spatio-temporal relationship between processes that I will label the network.  Networks, as they will be understood in this project, are fully theoretic constructs.  They arise from the theoretic abstraction of sites from structured totality and the subsequent (partial) reassembly of sites and their processes to articulate a particular geography and a particular temporal sequence or simultaneity, reflecting a structural relationship between the processes and processual sites contained by the network.  In this sense, the conception of networks used here remains at a relatively abstract, ontological level, encompassing any articulated spatio-temporal connection between material processes, not simply relationships defined by the presence of intervening physical infrastructures (e.g. an electrical grid or a mass transit system).[4]  The spatio-temporal connections between separate but functionally related chemically transformative processes in a photosynthesizing plant, thus, constitutes a network in the same way that the spatio-temporal connections between separate but interrelated financial processes involving multiple firms constitutes a different kind of network, constructed by a different theoretic process.

In order to emphasize the theoretic transformation of relations between sites in the articulation of the network relative to relations in structured totality, I will apply the concept of the node to describe particular sites contained by the network.  Nodes contain within their dimensions processes that are organic to the network as the spatio-temporal analog of a structure.  Nodes may also contain the sites of processes that are not connected theoretically to the processual structure defining the network.  For example, a production node in a network defined by a class structure (i.e. the site of production in a class structure articulated spatio-temporally as a network) contains a wide range of physical and social processual sites that do not define the class structure, even though these processes are overdeterminants of the class process of production.  The larger point, in this respect, is that the articulation of networks through the linking of nodes does not proceed from a general assumption of overdetermination between all processes (as on the field of structured totality), but necessitates the theoretic specification of linkages between processes and their spatio-temporal dimensions.  Networks may connect spatially dispersed nodes configured as archipelagos of processual sites, interspersed by processual sites wholly disconnected from the network as it is theoretically articulated in abstraction from the infinity of processual overdeterminants by which it is constituted.  

            With specific regard to the spatiality of networks and their respective nodes, some nodes will be relatively stationary over given periods of time while others are relatively mobile.[5]  Considered, again, strictly with respect to the spatial dimension, this must be the case if the processes defining the network are not spatially collocated.  The spatial dispersion of network processes implies that some processes, internal to the network, must connect relatively stationary and spatially separated processes.  A type of mobile node must exist to facilitate the transmission of effects between stationary nodes, a node defined by its processual role in the transmission of effects.  Extending this logic to the temporal dimensions of a network, if processes in a network are collocated but not simultaneous or sequential (i.e. separated by extended temporal ranges), then the network requires a node defined by its processual role in the transmission of effects between separated temporal instances.  The point is the same for networks defined strictly in reference to spatiality, strictly in reference to temporality, or in reference to some complex relationship of space and time: stationary nodes in a dispersed processual relationship require a vehicle for the transmission of specified effects across spaces or times not otherwise articulated within the network.

            A relatively simple relationship between a set of processes may illustrate the understanding that I mean to convey about relatively stationary and relatively mobile nodes.  Visual observation of objects by a human observer involves an integrated set of processes, characterized by spatial and temporal dispersion, constituting a network.  In spatial terms, the process involves two relatively stationary nodes: the object (constituted by a set of internal and external physical and social processes that overdetermine its existence as an object in continuous material transformation) and the human observer (constituted by a set of internal and external physical and social processes that overdetermine its existence as a human individual in continuous material transformation).  The spatial distance between the two relatively stationary nodes constitutes a pathway for the transmission of effects, but this pathway is constituted by processes (e.g. chemical transformation of molecules in air) incidental to the theoretically defined structure of processes in visual observation.  What is needed is a processual vehicle to connect the object to the observer.  This processual vehicle arises from the reflection of visible light waves off the surface of the object.  The process of visible light radiation, capturing the effects of processes constituting the object, thus, constitutes a transmission process between the relatively stationary nodes in the network.  The spatio-temporality of light particle transmission from the object, varying in accordance with the speed of light waves in continuous reaction with the physical and chemical processes of the pathway, exists as a mobile node in the network, carrying effects between stationary points.  A simple articulation of the network, abstracting from the complexities involved in optical processes or interpretation of visually accumulated information, is completed in the absorption of visible light waves by the observer’s eye. 

In order to further explain the meaning of the network in relation to the particular kinds of processes with which this project and Marxian theory, as a whole, are especially concerned, the class structure defined in chapter 1 provides an important example.  Again, the understanding of class structures followed within this project involves the integration of a particular set of class processes (the production, appropriation, distribution, and receiving of surplus labor) and the connections to non-class processes securing conditions of existence for the production and appropriation of surplus labor.  Class processes contained by a given class structure may take place at a variety of spatial locations and temporal instances.  The spatio-temporal relationships between these organic, relatively stationary processes, connected by mobile transmission processes, define a particular network, the class network. 

To present an example, a particular commodity-producing firm, defined by a class structure, produces commodities at a given spatial location over a particular period in time.  The production process involves the physical transformation of certain raw material use values into a different set of use values, but it additionally involves the production of surplus value through the exploitation of labor power to produce an additional realizable value embodied in finished commodities exceeding the exchange value of the tools, equipment, raw materials, and labor power utilized in production.  Again, following Ruccio et al (1991), this site is simultaneously the site at which the firm appropriates surplus values, contained as values congealed in a mass of finished use values.  The realization of these surplus values in a monetary form occurs through market exchange.  It is conceivable that this realization process occurs at the same site as the site of production/appropriation, but I will assume, for my purposes, that the commodities must be relocated to a different site for market exchange.  Upon realizing the surplus values contained by the commodities through exchange, the appropriator/distributors of the firm receive the realized surplus values, perhaps with a deduction reflecting a surplus distribution to secure the realization process (e.g. to a retailer).  This receipt of surplus value may, again, occur at any site, but I will assume that it occurs at a site that is distinct either from the site of production/appropriation or the site of market exchange/realization, necessitating some forms of financial transmission to the site of initial receipt and distribution.   

The combination of these processes conveys a particular temporal sequence of events (production/appropriation – realization – receiving) and a particular geography (site of production/appropriation - site of realization – site of initial receiving).  It also involves transmission processes with relatively mobile sites (e.g. site of physical commodity transportation from the production/appropriation site to the site of realization; site of electronic transmission of financial information from the site of realization to the site of receiving).  By articulating all of these processes as an integrated structure of processes (i.e. a class structure) and applying a set of spatio-temporal relations (simultaneity, sequence, collocation, proximity, dispersion) between the sites of these processes, I articulate the structure as a network and redefine the sites as nodes within the network. 

Elaborating, I can further extend the network by adding other conditions of existence for the production and appropriation of surplus value (i.e. other than market realization).[6]  Such processes as the provision of financing to undertake the production process may, for example, involve processes (e.g. lending by financial institutions) wholly separated from the sites of production/appropriation, realization, and initial receiving of surplus value by the appropriator/distributors.  The financial process is connected, structurally, to the class structure through the distribution and receiving of surplus value in the form of interest payments.  The distribution and receiving of these payments may have their own spatio-temporalities, separated spatially and/or temporally from the appropriation of surplus value, and the receiving of surplus values in the form of interest payments by financial institutions may be spatially and/or temporally separated from other processes involved in financial lending to secure the financial conditions of existence for the firm to undertake production.

Elaborating still further, the transmission processes within the network may connect to myriad other processes, otherwise disconnected from the network, if these transmission processes result in certain metaphorical leaks.  That is to say, if the transmission process between stationary nodes results in non-negligible effects to the pathways along which transmissions take place, then the class processes in the network will be affected in ways that can be explicitly theorized.  To provide a very tangible example, if commodity transportation processes between a production/appropriation node and an exchange node by means of a waterborne freight process results in ecological damage (e.g. contamination of water from an actual fuel leak), then the class network will be shaped by the interaction of economic, political, and cultural processes resulting from such an event.  Every process connected to the network as a result of the event possesses its own spatio-temporality, implying that for every such event, new stationary and mobile transmission nodes must be connected to the network.   

In specifying the spatio-temporal relationships contained by this class network, the spatio-temporality of all stationary nodes has to be specified and mobile nodes for the transmission of effects along pathways must also be specified in order to theoretically articulate a definitive relationship between these processes that is performative of the reality that Marxian theory means to convey.  For every new processual connection specified, a new, stationary node is added to the network, connected by some transmission node.  In this manner, the construction of the class network is piecewise.  It does not saturate geographies with explosively diffusive connections, but reconstructs spatio-temporal relationships between particular processes one connection at a time. 
            To summarize, the network concept, as I have presented it, describes a theoretic articulation of sites, extracted from structured totality, containing processes whose integration defines a structure.  The theoretic repositioning of sites in this articulation transforms each site into a node.  Spatial and/or temporal dispersion of processes within networks necessitates that some nodes will be relatively stationary while other will be relatively mobile, facilitating connections across spatial or temporal pathways between the stationary nodes of the network.  This understanding seeks to preserve the processual understanding of material existence advanced by Marxian theory and the definition of space-time as the dimensions of processes.  If all space-time exists as a dimension of processes and structurally integrated processes exist in a spatially dispersed organization, with intervening spaces constituted by processes unrelated in theory, then the connections between structurally related processes must require some means to facilitate the transmission of effects between sites/nodes. 


[1] This understanding of time, as a dimension of process in an overdeterminist ontology, corresponds to Althusser’s assertion of heterogeneous specificities of the historical temporality of different “levels” within a Marxist totality (Althusser and Balibar, 2009: 110-111).
[2]  This concept of the site corresponds, in part, to the site concept advanced by Resnick and Wolff (1987: 231-232), defined as “a location or grouping of specific relationships that each comprise a particular subset of social and natural processes.”  The definition advanced by this project, on the other hand, seeks to advance a more specific spatio-temporal definition of the site arising from a relational logic of space-time.  In this manner, the site concept introduced here is read as a geographically and historically specified and bounded location defined by the spatio-temporality of processes both internal and external to a set of boundaries defined by the process. 
[3] Such a locus might be characterized, as in Resnick and Wolff (1987: 25-30), as an entry point, in contrast to an ontologically prioritized causal essence.
[4] This level of theoretic abstraction, further, contrasts with the use of the network concept by Castells (2000A:163-215), who uses it describe information flows in globally extensive capitalist firms, and by Hardt and Negri, who variously employ the concept in the same manner as Castells (Hardt and Negri, 2001: 294-300), to describe the expansiveness of the U.S. imperial sovereignty (Ibid, 164-167), and to describe the organizational styles of al-Qaeda, the Zapatistas, and the “movement of movements” against capitalist globalization (2004: 54-57, 79-91).  
[5] The stationary property of certain network nodes is only “relative” because the geometry and geographic positioning of processual space is continuously relational (i.e. the space of every process is continuously defined by its changing position relative to other processes).  In this sense, the network presupposes the capacity of theory to freeze a temporal moment or a sequence of moments in order to articulate the spatiality of a set of relations between a specified set of processes in a structure.   
[6] Resnick and Wolff (1987: 174-180) elaborate a list of such subsumed class processes, involving the distribution of surplus values to non-productive agents (i.e. those not producing realizable surplus values but performing other necessary work) inside and outside of a firm.

No comments:

Post a Comment