Thursday, March 3, 2022

Introducing Marxism and the City in Globalization VII (Conclusion)

Thesis: The Heterogeneity of Class Structures in Globalizing Cities

The first section of this chapter concluded with the claim that the central commonality evident in the various approaches to the city in Marxist and Marxian-inspired theories is that the contemporary city is conceived as a capitalist city.  Numerous accounts advance such a conclusion quite explicitly.  For example, Harvey argues, in reference to the variety of technological changes reducing the temporal requirements of movement across space (i.e. space-time compression), that:

These new technological and organizational possibilities have all been produced under the impulsions of a capitalist mode of production with its hegemonic military-industrial-financial interests.  For this reason, I believe it is not only useful to think of but also important to recognize that we are all embroiled in a global process of capitalist urbanization or uneven spatio-temporal development even in those countries that have nominally at least sought a noncapitalistic path of development and a noncapitalist urban form (1996: 414, italics in original).   

The implication of this reasoning is that capital accumulation in diverse production processes and the particular effects of technological development arising from such processes imprint the image of a globally expansive capitalist mode of production upon all social contexts with which they come into contact, notwithstanding the efforts of policymakers to displace axiomatic dependence on capitalism.  In reference to the city, as a spatial form, the impact of capital accumulation, both in the development of urban built form and the integration of technologies into the everyday lives of urban residents, ensures that every city in the age of a specifically capitalist globalization, marked by the insistent penetration of capital accumulation into new geographies, must be a capitalist city.  Harvey’s characterization of the relationship of capitalism to urbanization can be described as capitalocentric, using Gibson-Graham’s (2006A) terminology.     

            The capitalocentric characteristics evident in the larger body of Marxist and Marxian-inspired theories on the city manifest diverse forms, introducing divergent consequences for the relationship between theory and urban practice.  As suggested in the previous section, theories focusing on the relationship of class struggle to the development of urban social movements manifest a particular reduction of class to the binary struggle of unitary working and capitalist classes, a binary constituted by the image of a capitalist mode of production that is singular and coextensive with economic processes such that every form of workplace involved in commodity production can be labeled capitalist.  The commitment of agency-oriented theorists to ontologically privilege individual agency relative to structural determination implies that such discourses do not, however, typically go as far in expanding the sphere of effects from capitalism as more structurally oriented theorists like Harvey, the regional economy theorists, or the control and coordination (global and world city) theorists. 

To varying degrees, structurally oriented approaches to the city expand the social effects of capitalist processes to suggest, in many cases, a kind of uni-directional determination of political, cultural, and ecological processes by the economic, at a minimum arguing that state policies in urban planning or collective consumption and the development of alternative non-class cultural self-identifications must be functional to capitalist development and reproduction.  Further, reflecting on the position of the city relative to other geographic scales, the reduction of the city to a limited set of political/institutional roles by the regional economy theorists, alluded to in the first section in reference to Scott et al (2008), introduces a kind of inter-scalar economic determination of the local (i.e. the city) by the regional and/or the global, in which the latter, higher scales articulate restructuring processes by industrial capitalism.  In this sense, capitalism, as the economic, is uniquely capable of transcending the limitations of local space and even regional and national space to become global.  Thus, the city becomes a captive of regional and/or global economic processes that are unambiguously capitalist. 

Structurally oriented manifestations of capitalocentrism and the reduction of class to the working/capitalist class binary ultimately reflect the utilization of definitions for capitalism that are sufficient broad to subsume not only a range of effects on non-economic processes, but to subsume the totality of economic processes and to reduce the possibility or actual presence of alternative organizations of surplus labor to relatively minor variations on a common capitalist logic of commodity production and/or market exchange under the motive of profit.  Capitalism, thus, completely encompasses the horizon of feasible economic structures and this coextensive identity of the economic with capitalism constitutes the hegemonic influence of capitalism on political, cultural, and physical/ecological processes.  Consequently, socially transformative projects, contesting the effects of capitalist economic processes, confront an expressive totality of social processes, all arrayed to reproduce the hegemony of capitalism.  For this reason, the sorts of capitalocentric discourse represented in most of the aforementioned Marxian theories of the city impose on socially transformative urban movements, especially those anchored on the historically assigned agency of the working class, the impossible task of overthrowing, in its entirety, a globally integrated system from the standpoint of the local/the city.         

Consistent with its theoretic bases in the Marxian theory of class, Althusserian overdeterminist ontology, and performative epistemology, this project rejects this capitalocentric imagery.  Elaborating, overdeterminist ontology holds that capitalist class processes are mutually constituted by and mutually constitutive of all other social and physical processes, implying that no uni-directional determinism is conceivable.  As such, the structured totality of processes containing capitalist class processes manifests complexity, irreducible to the simple expression of capitalist dominance in all its processual parts. 

Addressing the geographic/scalar imagery of global capitalist dominance and ontological captivity of cities relative to the regional or the global scale, this project will advance a theory of networks in chapter 2 with the intention of reframing the geography of the city in relation to material processes.  This network imagery will insist that spatial scales are constituted as piecewise constructs of relatively local processes, local in the sense that every process has a definite positionality and boundedness relative to other processes for any given moment in time.  The global scale of social processes exists as a piecewise combination of local processes whose effects diffuse explosively but unevenly along complex but fragile networks.  Consistent with overdeterminist ontology, such networks must, likewise, facilitate multi-directional effects.  Thus, the effects of globally dispersed capitalist class processes on a particular city cannot be understood, on the one hand, as uni-directional (from transnational capitalist firms to individual cities) or, on the other hand, as emanating from a unitary global agency (from the global to the local) rather than as an assemblage of networked but dispersed local processes.  Such an understanding of connections, not between the local and the global but between diverse locals across networks that facilitate multidirectional linkages, imposes the sort of relational logic discussed earlier in which every process is understood to define its own scale and agents interact simultaneously through multiple local, regional, and globally-extensive networks defined by processes.

Finally, and most importantly for the hypothesis that I mean to initially advance here and subsequently to elaborate in chapter 3, this project contests the ambiguity with which capitalism has been defined and ascribed a substantive influence on a wide range of social processes in the theoretic approaches heretofore described.  Capitalism, as it is variously defined implicitly or explicitly, describes market exchange processes, the integration, expansion, and transformation of social divisions of labor with respect to production processes and geographic regions, the supremacy of the profit motive in driving entrepreneurship, or the evolving technical, bureaucratic, and geographic organization of enterprises.  If, in some sense, all of these potential definitions of capitalism describe economic processes, they are all too broad and diffuse to convey the unique insights that Marxian theory has to offer on class in general or on capitalism in particular.  They truncate the theoretic spaces for identification of economic non-capitalisms.

The first step in moving beyond this capitalocentric logic involves providing a definition of capitalism consistent with Althusserian overdeterminism.  Applying, again, the definitions of class structure types conveyed by Resnick and Wolff (1987), capitalism constitutes a particular exploitative class structure in which the producers of surplus labor supply their capacity to do work to a capitalist appropriator/distributor as commodity labor power in market exchange.  In exchange for wage-based compensation, producers produce a value in excess of the value of the labor compensation/wages (a surplus value), contained in a mass of commodities and realizable through exchange.  Upon realization of the value contained in the commodities, the capitalist appropriator/distributor determines the necessary distributions that must be undertaken in order to secure conditions of existence of the surplus production process so that it can be successfully reproduced over time. 

This modest definition describes and delimits capitalism as a class structure in such a way that certain class structures, existing simultaneously to capitalism cannot be described as capitalist.  Specifically, surplus production processes in which the producer and appropriator/distributor are identical and singular describe non-capitalist ancient class structures.  Surplus production processes in which the producers and appropriator/distributors are identical and plural describe non-capitalist communist class structures.  In both of these cases, means for the compensation of labor power, the realization of values, and the technical organization of production processes are incidental to the organization of surplus labor that defines the class structure.  Thus, ancient and communist class structures may produce commodities for market exchange and operate as firms, in a legal and proprietary sense, but market and legal/proprietary processes do not render them capitalist. 

By utilizing a definition of capitalism that relates it, as a class structure, to a very specific form in the organization of surplus labor, I am able to advance the outlines of a hypothesis.  Cities, as spatial forms, contain diverse ranges of social processes, organized ontologically into structures of related processes and spatially and temporally linked as networks.  Some of these networks are contained within the city and others extend longer distances beyond the variously defined boundaries of the city.  Some of these social processes are class processes.  Among the class processes, some are capitalist class processes.  On the other hand, the class processes and the structures and networks that they define are not exclusively capitalist.  There are slave, feudal, ancient, and communist processes as well.  All of these processes operate simultaneously.  Their structures are also typically interlinked and their spatial networks overlap.  In addition, capitalist class structures are not exclusive in producing networks that extend beyond the boundaries of a city.  Other types of class structures produce their own interregional class networks and non-class processes produce interregional non-class process networks (e.g. ethnic-cultural processes, political processes, etc.).  These preliminary assertions mean to posit the city as a spatial form existing as a piece-wise ensemble of processes, structures, and, spatio-temporally, networks and to argue suggestively that the existence of heterogeneous class structures in cities is important in shaping the city as something other than a purely capitalist city.  That is to say, the existence of non-capitalist class structures, especially non-exploitative communist class structures, shapes the economic, political, cultural, and ecological processes of the city. 

Further, in conformity with a performative epistemological framework, by positing the existence of non-capitalist class structures in cities, I mean to reinforce the potentiality for cities to nurture such structures.  In this sense, the theorization of non-capitalist structures as actually existing entities in cities and theorization of conditions of existence for such structures does not simply generate an empirically testable hypothesis for examination of cities, in the sense that Castells’ theorization of the relationship between collective consumption and urban social movements had motivated his empirical scholarship of the late 1970s.  Rather, this project seeks to contribute to a continuously evolving Marxian strategy to develop communist class structures in cities as practical alternatives to capitalism. 

            In, thus, departing from the capitalocentric logic of other Marxian approaches to the city, this account means to take Katznelson’s advice that Marxism indeed needs to exhibit a greater degree of modesty in approaching its revolutionary aims.  In contrast to Katznelson’s approach, however, the sort of modesty that this project seeks to cultivate concerns the scale of communist society envisioned by theory.  The sort of communisms envisioned by this project possess no pretension of overthrowing en masse capitalist class structures and all of the non-class structures supporting the reproduction of such structures.  On the contrary, this project understands communist revolution as a continuous and tenuous piece-wise endeavor of collective entrepreneurship and class and non-class network building in which cities play an important role.  For that reason, this project seeks to situate the city, as an interregionally connective space, in relation to class and to advance a more modest appraisal of the possibilities for a more modest communism than that advanced, implicitly or explicitly, in alternative Marxist approaches.

No comments:

Post a Comment